After reading Plato’s Gorgias,
I was left a bit dissatisfied and confused. Socrates tags rhetoric as “a
craftsman of persuasion,” but an actual definition is never revealed (453a).
Granted, I am not sure a concrete definition of rhetoric would ever be
possible. I found myself shaking my head when certain arguments developed such
as Socrates’ assertion that it is better to suffer injustice instead of doing
the injustice. Reading Kastely’s article helped put the work into perspective
concerning the historical context surrounding the characters.
Kastely states:“Gorgias seeks to justify rhetoric by its
communal utility, while Polus and Callicles admire it for its ability to confer
power on the individual agent” (98). The
communal aspect becomes lost as Socrates argues with Polus and Callicles and
leaves Gorgias behind. The arguments then become muddled within issues such as
nature and convention. Callicles states it this way:
“For, Socrates, you
really lead the discussion into such tiresome things, suited to a popular
speaker—while claiming to pursue the truth—things that are not fine by nature,
but by convention. And in most cases these things are opposed to each other,
nature and convention” (482e).
Kastely points out the philosophical idea that “we can never
arrive at a natural state,” because we are influenced by culture (102). This
influence is known in politics, especially, and adds to the concern of rhetoric
being a useful tool or just a means of gaining power. The complexities of the
different arguments are identified in what Kastely calls a “philosophical
rhetoric”(100). In Gorgias, Callicles
compares philosophy with “something slavish” in that it is almost like a game
(485b). Socrates even adds to this idea in the following exchange in lines 490a:
CAL.: How you always
say the same things, Socrates!
SOC.: Not only that, Callicles, but also about the
same things.
Engaging in these kinds of discussions led me to think of a
scene in The Princess Bride in which
Westley challenges Vizzini in a “battle of wits” over a cup of poisonous wine.
Vizzini even references Plato, Socrates, and Aristotle and makes it known that
their intellect does not compare to his. Starting around 1:23, Vizzini gives a
“dizzying” speech about where the poison resides and thus offers reasons why he
would choose neither the cup in front of him nor Westley. He draws on
contextual clues such as the poison’s country of origin and his claim that
Westley must be a “clever man.” He then resorts to trickery as he switches the
cups while Westley turns his head. However, Vizzini’s tactics do not work,
because what he does not realize is that Westley had built up immunity to the
poison and thus defeats Vizzini.
http://youtu.be/U_eZmEiyTo0
Vizzini attempts to think critically about his situation,
but it is of naught once he takes a sip of the wine. His confusing words are
playfully styled after those of Socrates, but they present a significant
question: Are humans afraid to “engage critically” (106)? Because we are shaped
so much by ideologies, it is easy for beliefs to become rigid and unquestioned.
According to Kastely, “rhetoric needs to undertake the more difficult task of
making us available for dialectical refutation” (106). Callicles and Polus
clearly backed away from this idea, thus causing their discussions with Socrates
to become dissatisfying. After reading
both Gorgias and Kastely’s article, I
am left with this thought to ponder: One must be open to criticism, and it is
the power of rhetoric that allows this openness. And in return, this openness will lead to
greater truth or perhaps more confusion.
Stephanie, what a great connection! This is an all-time favorite movie of mine and I forgot about this scene. It's ironic that Vizzini mentions Plato and Socrates by name here.
ReplyDelete